Ôèëîëîãè÷åñêèå íàóêè/3.Òåîðåòè÷åñêèå ïðîáëåìû èññëåäîâàíèÿ

Blagodarna O.M.

Karazin Kharkiv National University

THE CONCEPT “WORK” AS A CATEGORIZED STRUCTURE

Concept analysis is a crucial point in modern cognitive linguistics. The present abstract dwells on the methods of concept representation, because “the issue of method deals with the issue of content and reality of a concept itself” [2: 25]. The authors give a general overlook of categorization phenomenon and describe the procedure of the concept WORK categorization analysis. 

Categorization makes it possible for an organism to reduce limitless variations in the world to manageable proportions. A category fulfils this function in virtue of the fact that “by knowing the category to which a thing belongs, the organism, thereby, knows as many attributes as possible” [6: 197]. Because classical and prototypical organization of categories are considered to be the most constructive and coherent ones, we will introduce these two approaches into out research. 

As for classical categories, it is well known that Aristotle distinguished between the essence of a thing and its accidents. The essence is that which makes a thing what is it, all immanent parts which define and indicate their individuality. Accidents are incidental properties which play no part in determining what a thing is [8: 22-23]. In this case, once established, classical category divides the universe into two sets of entities – those that are members of the category and those that are not.

The inadequacies of the classical theory were broadly represented for the first time in “Philosophical Inversigations” by L. Wittgenstein, who analyzed the definition cases of the word Spiel “game” [9]. He notes that there are no common properties shared by all members of the GAME category. Thus, the fact of inability to differentiate clearly games from non-games proves the hypothesis of fuzzy category boundaries.

E. Rosh proved that certain kinds of entities could be regarded as good examples in a category and that category membership degree is a psychologically valid notion [5; 6]. As studied by E. Rosh, prototypicality is bound up with what might be called “two axes of categorization” [8: 46]. The horizontal axis represents contrasting categories whereas the vertical axis unites categories that share at least one common attribute.

It is clear that not all the category levels are of the same importance for the speaker. The more cognitively and linguistically salient level of categorization, as noticed by E. Rosch, is its “basic level”. It is at the basic level of categorization that people conceptualize thing as perceptual and functional gestalts [7]. In this connection it seems not out of place to mention the assumption of R.W. Langacker, exposed in his work “Foundation of Cognitive Grammar”. Particularly, he argues that cognitive structures often need to be understood more as holistic, gestalt configurations, than as attribute bundles [4: 19].

The above-given overlook enables us to claim that the concept WORK is a categorical concept of basic level, which means that it possesses the necessary properties of a category, such as holistic nature and perceptual and functional simplicity. According to the prior analysis [1], the concept WORK is based on a complex prototypical model, the nucleus of which is represented by the following frame [the SUBJECT of the action – produces mental and/or physical ACTIVITY – in order to get tangible/intangible RESULT]. The periphery is represented by properties that are metonymically attached to the nucleus, i.e. OBJECT towards the activity is directed, PLACE where it is happening, TIME during which it is happening and INSTRUMENT required to carry out the activity.

In the framework of our research the basic category WORK might be considered as a superordinate category that unites all cognitive models of its subordinate categories – i.e. a cluster of models.  Conventional variations of the central case, i.e. subordinate categories, are determined by one of the cognitive models and make a deviation from the central prototypical model. The subordinate categories are as follows:  ACTIVITY, RESULT (which are considered as central subcategories) and OBJECT, TIME, PLACE, INSTRUMENT (which are considered as peripheral subcategories).

The basic level category WORK is represented by two salient dimensions:  dynamic (ACTIVITY) and static (RESULT). Each dimension is represented by two cognitive models, each model highlighting a different aspect of WORK concept. The cognitive model is represented by its central member – a lexeme that possesses prototypical attributes of the category-member and its proper attributes. Thus, the peripheral groups of lexemes are tugged to the central lexeme by partial confluence of different numbers of attributes.

The ACTIVITY dimension is structured by two cognitive models. The first model [WORK is an EFFORT] represents WORK as “the active use of mental power or physical strength in producing a result”. The central lexeme labour is surrounded by peripheral groups of lexemes: pain-struggle-travail, with additional semes ”onerous and painful”; drudgery-grind-toil with additional semes “exhausting, irksome and monotonous”. The second model [WORK is MEANS OF EARNING INCOME] represents WORK as “the activity by which one regularly makes a living”. The centre of the model is marked by the lexeme occupation. The three peripheral groups are interconnected by gradual highlighting of the semes combination “presence employer/ remuneration/ motivation”: employment-job-office-position; craft-line-métier-pursuit-trade-vocation; chore-duty-endeavour-mission-task-undertaking. 

The static dimension RESULT is structured by two cognitive models, those of [WORK is an INTANGIBLE RESULT] and [WORK is a TANGIBLE RESULT]. There is no lexeme other than work to represent the former model.  The latter model is formed by two central lexemes which, in their turn, determine the periphery.  The lexeme composition denotes “output of inspiration”. One peripheral group shares the seme “arrangement”: configuration-design-form-layout-pattern; and “output of artistic excellence”: article-essay-etude-magnum opus-masterpiece-model-novel-paper-pièce de résistance-showpiece-sketch-story. The lexeme product has nearest periphery is formed by the lexemes article-goods-merchandise-wares, that share the common attribute “commercial use” and the lexemes fruit-handwork-object-thing-yield for “non-commercial use”.

As we can see, the basic-level concept WORK is subject to vertical and horizontal categorization. Superior categories contain cognitive models that are projected on the subordinate level categories. The categories of subordinate level might serve as superordinate categories for the lower levels of categorization. Because of the fuzziness of category boundaries all the categories are inter-connected.  As the further trend of out research we plan to study the functioning of the concept WORK categories in discourse.  

References:

1. Áëàãîäàðíà Î.Ì. Ñåìàíòèêî-êîãí³òèâíèé àíàë³ç ³ìåí ë³íãâîêóëüòóðíîãî êîíöåïòó "ðîáîòà" (íà ìàòåð³àë³ àíãëîìîâíîãî õóäîæíüîãî äèñêóðñó) // ³ñíèê Õàðê³âñüêîãî íàö³îíàëüíîãî óí³âåðñèòåòó ³ì. Â.Í. Êàðàç³íà. – 2006.  ¹ 741. – Ñ. 38-41.

2. Ñòåïàíîâ Þ.Ñ. Êîíñòàíòû: Ñëîâàðü ðóññêîé êóëüòóðû. – Ì.: ßçûêè ðóñ. êóëüòóðû, 1997. – Ñ. 26. 

3. Geeraerts D. Cognitive restrictions on the structure of semantic change. In J. Fisiak (ed.), Historical Semantics, Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, 1985. – P. 127-153.

4. Langacker R.W. Foundations of Cognitive Grammar, Theoretical Prerequisites. – Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1987.

5. Rosch E. On the internal structure of perceptual and semantic categories. In Moore, 1973. – P. 111-114.

6. Rosch E. Universals and cultural specifics in human categorization. In R.W.Brislin, S.Bochner, and W.J.Lonner (eds.), Cross-cultural Perspectives on Learning. – New York: John Wiley, 1975. – P. 177-206.

7. Rosch E. Structural bases of typicality effects. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 2, 1976. – P. 491-502.

8. Taylor J.R. Linguistic Categorization. Prototypes in Linguistic Theory. – Oxford: Claredon Press, 1995. – 312 p.  

9. Wittgenstein L., Philosophical investigations. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe.  Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1978.