Titarenko I.N.
The Stoic Conception of a Language
and Problems of Modern Linguistics and Cognitive Anthropology
Learning
a language represents a field of interdisciplinary investigations, where
philosophers, linguists, logicians, psychologists, cultural researchers and
other scientists put their effort. This is not unexpected since a researcher
who turns to investigating a natural language would be unable to avoid dealing
with such questions as the relationship between a language, thought and
reality, uncovering the human cognition mechanisms, cross-cultural
communication, influence of a language upon the peculiarity of the way every
ethnic group perceives the reality, etc. Analyzing a language as a means of
communication that is a sign system, which allows us to pick out and identify
objects of the environment, to generalize their features and formulate some
abstract ideas provides us with a deep insight into the human nature. A man,
being a part of the society, and being endowed with reason expresses his
individuality as well as thought processes through language forms. As the
result of this fact, the present-day branches of science dealing with
linguistics (such as psycholinguistics, sociolinguistics and others) tend to
follow the anthropological paradigm, which calls for synthesizing the proper
vocabulary system analysis and philosophical knowledge about a man as a
conscious social and cultural being. On the other hand, philosophical
anthropology claims a thorough analysis of a language, its structure and its
functions.
Nevertheless,
it should be pointed out, that it was quite a long time ago that the thinkers
came to the necessity of a language in-depth analysis. As an example, we can
refer to the linguistic philosophy of the Stoics. The ideas of its representatives,
namely Zeno, Chrysippus and Diogenes of
Babylon are traditionally studied not
only in the course of history of philosophy but also in the history of
linguistics course as they created an integrated system of knowledge about a
language, regarding the latter as a display of reason. At the same time the
Stoics doctrine was based upon the linguistic information, and primarily on
semantic syntax
All the
linguistic ideas were traditionally stated within their logic theory. Logic was
an essential part of their doctrine directly linked with physics and ethic
[Diogenes Laertius, 7, 40]. It was to fulfill the functions of general
propaedeutics and epistemology and the whole Stoic Orthodox doctrine was as a
rule preceded and guided by logic. Unfortunately, time has damaged greatly the
logic part of the stoics' doctrine. Their logic terminology is fairly difficult
and due to the fact that the early stoics' works have been lost and the later
Stoics were not so interested in logic, so we can judge on their ideas of logic
only relying upon some second-hand sources which are often but fragmentary.
However, the logic part of the Stoic philosophy has been reconstructed [1],
fairly well, which enables us to study and to analyze the remaining ideas of
the stoics about language.
The
Stoics' logic was divided into two main clusters – rhetoric as an art of
persuasion and dialectics, which included grammar (the theory of the signifier)
and formal logic (as the theory of the signified). Their study on the criterion
of cognition and on ways of definitions classifications are sometimes stated as
separate theories.
According
to the Stoics, world cognition starts with sense perception, and its
information coming through senses that become the primordial material for
thought. Before any sense experience, «the man's soul is a blank slate, ready
for inscriptions» [2]. From the information supplied by perception through
pneuma to the supervising centre, an impression in the soul is formed (phantasia) [SVF I, 58]. At the same
time, the Stoics are convinced that a man's senses do not deceive him, so they
cannot be estimated as true or false. The factor of truth or error can be
applied only to a statement, which needs to be agreed with, the agreement being
a preliminary estimate of the statement meaning, (but not the impression
itself). Agreement represents the ability of analyzing and estimating the
statement about the impressions. As a result of this analysis a conception (êatalepsis) should be created, that is coming to
understanding of the material nature of an object.
The
question of the perception criterion (the origin of knowledge criterion) [3],
is rather complicated and its decision is linked to a number of problems, since
the early Stoics were unable to find a definite answer to the question whether
perception, experience or the so-called «cataleptic impression» (the immediate
discretion) should be accepted as the perception criterion. However that may
be, the sequences of the uniform impressions coming to a person form experience,
which leads to creating conceptions, retaining the general hallmarks of the
sequences [Seneca. Ep., 120, 4-5]. So, when describing the process of creating
general conceptions the Stoics tend to be nominalists.
The
most important subject that attracted particular interest within the dialectics
as the crucial part of the Stoic logic was the relationship between the
signifier and the signified, that is «the theory of signs». The early Stoic
emphasized the correlation between the sign itself (the signifier – to sēmainon) the meaning (the
signified – to lecton) and the object
(to tygchanon). The sign and the
object were considered corporeal while the meaning was incorporeal. Thus, the
Stoic based their dialectics on the ideas of the sign nature of knowledge, that
is they considered it necessary to distinguish within the act of speech the
signifier or the pronounced sound and the signified or the meaning of what is
pronounced as a link between a thought and a sound.
These
ideas prove that the Stoic were the first to propose the notion of the sign of
a language and thus to initiate the semiotic theory of language.
The
early Stoic ideas on relation between a sign, meaning and an object can be
found in the works of the late stoicism representative and a Roman philosopher
Seneca: «There are bodies of different origin: for example this is a man and
this is a horse. These are immediately followed by the soul's excitation which
announces a body (has deinde sequuntur
motus animorum enuntiativi corporum). These soul excitations represent
something independent, not connected with the bodies. (hi habent proprium quiddam et a corporibus seductumi). I see Cato
walking. My perception showed me this (hoc sensus ostendit), and my soul
believed it (animus credidit). What I see is a body (ñorpus
est quod video), which I examined with my eyes and my reason. (cui et oculos intendi et animum). And so I say: "Cato is
walking"» [Seneca. Ep., 117, 13]. There is an object of cognition – some
situation or phenomenon of the world. As a result of its impact upon our organs
of perception, for example an eye as in the stated case, we get some idea or
image, which is later conceived in or soul (namely in our mind) and thus we get
the ideal meaning or the contents of knowledge which eventually grows into a
judgment. The meaning of the utterance is incorporeal. «What I am saying now is
not in the least a body, but it is something that announces a body (non corpus, inquit, est, quod nunc loquor,
sed enuntiativum quiddam de corpore)» [Seneca. Ep., 117, 13]. As it can be
clearly seen here in treating this question Seneca follows the dogma of his
doctrine and makes almost no alterations in Stoic ideas of incorporeal meaning,
identified by the ancient Greeks as to lecton [4]. He finds difficulty in rendering
this term into Latin: «Some call it “outspoken” (effatum), others think a term “announced” (enuntiatum), is more suitable, and others call it “said” (edictum)» [Seneca. Ep., 117, 13].
The
difference between the meaning and the sound is transmitted by is regarded by
the Stoic as the difference between the endophasia or internalspeech (logos endiathetos) and the external or
the pronounced (logos prophoricos)
speech. Endophasia is a set of meanings that is what we think of while
pronouncing the corresponding words. Only human beings are endowed with
endophasia (logos endiathetos),
though animals are also able to make sounds. Therefore, the language analysis
leads the Stoics to the problem of human nature and its peculiarities compared
to the nature of other living things. A sentient being is capable of passing
the contents of their conscience to other sentient beings by means of words.
Children (who are, according to the Stoics, devoid of reason) and animals do
not know the meanings and the correct words links, so they can only appeal to
the external form of speech, which is non-meaningful [Varr. De l. lat. VI, 56.].
The
correct implication on the meaning level (lekton) is a subjective guarantee of
the Universe being understood and includes fixing the causality [Sext. Adv. M.
VIII, 275-276]. The laws of language and thought do not determine the forms of
the Universe, but according to the Stoics, reveal the objective contents of the
cosmos. The human reason is a mere reflection of the Universal reason (logos) –
the only true guarantee of the objectivity and the integrity of the Universe.
For a Stoic philosopher nothing but truly cognized logic enables him to make
true conclusions concerning the world’s organizations and people’s behavior:
the order of and the interrelations between the meanings must be the same as
the order of and the interrelations between the «denotat». Strange as it might
seem to be, the problem of the correlation between the sign and the signified
object, which the ancient Greeks considered, still remains within the scope of
interests of contemporary logic, linguistics and semantics. It is particularly
interesting when applied to the analysis of the expressions used to indicate,
to name and to identify objects and concepts, which are in between the thought
and the world. The question is whether these expressions indicate the object by
means of a concept (Frege) or in a more direct way (Kaplan, Kripke, Putnam).
The
Stoic philosophy also treats the problem of cross-cultural communication which
is one of the major themes right up today for the representatives of the
cognitive anthropology. The incorporeal signified or the pure meanings are the
things, which are incomprehensible for the barbarians, as they hear the Greek
speech [Diogenes Laertius, VII, 55; Sext. Adv. M., VII, 38]. The fact that the
same meaning can be expressed with different words equals to the difference in
languages. Being sure of the entirety of the world guided by the Universal
reason, of the human conscious commonality and of the common logic world
structure the Stoic philosophers suggested the commonality of meanings,
expressed through different word combinations. At the same time, this theme was
particularly appealing when referring to the cosmopolitanism, proclaimed by the
Stoics. Contemporary cognitive anthropology and psycholinguistics have refused
these conclusions, which are too categorical. Today’s knowledge about the
relationship between the language, the culture and the thought give rise to the
idea that the ethnic differences in the uttered speech and in the sounding of
what we pronounce are determined by cultural differences in the environment
perception and estimation, hence in the meanings of what is said (to lecton).
Nevertheless,
the Stoic philosophy analysis makes an impressive case in favor of the fact
that various problems, touched upon by the Hellenic thinkers, have been
returned to and developed by the world’s philosophers of different times. And
though not all ideas were directly adopted, the range of problems discussed by
the Stoic philosophers within the language theory retain their importance for
contemporary science, which considers a language as an object to
interdisciplinary research.
Literature
1.
Mates B. Stoic Logic. Berkeley; Los Angeles, 1953; Barwick K. Probleme der
Stoischen Sprachlehre und Rhetorik. B., 1957; Bobzien S. Die Stoische
Modallogik. Würzburg, 1986; Egli U. Zur Stoischen Dialektik. Basel, 1967;
Frede M. Die Stoische Logik. Göttingen, 1974 etc.
2. Stoicorum veterum
fragmenta (SVF). Coll. I. ab Arnim. Vol. I-III. Lipsiae, 1903-1905; Vol. IV.
Indices, conscr. M. Adler. Lipsiae, 1924; Vol. I-IV. Leiden, 1964. – Vol. II,
83.
3.
More in detail see: Stoliarov A.A. Stoia and Stoicism. Moscow: «Kami
Group», 1998, p. 48-68.
4.
SVF II, 168; Sext. Emp. Adv. math. 8, 11-12. The ancient Stoic theory of
lecta is too complex and many-sided,
so it can’t be under consideration in this work. For further details see: Losev
A.F. The History of Ancient Aesthetics. The early Hellenic period. Moscow, 1979,
p. 87-91; Mates B. Stoic Logic. Berkeley, Los Angeles, 1953; Mau J. Stoische Logik//
Hermes. 85. 1957; Frege M. Die stoische Logik. Göttingen, 1974.